The Epic Identity of the Iliad and Odyssey: Pindar and Herodotus’ Lofty Legacy

The Homeric and Hindu epics appeal to their audiences as religious instructors by dint of addressing important existential issues in entertaining manners. Each pair of poems offers a couple of complementary solutions to a particularly pressing human problem. Because these solutions are found in the accounts that the epics place in the mouths of their poetic kings, accounts that mirror the epics in which they occur, understanding the relationship between the coupled epics in which the kings’ songs are embedded provides insight into the epics’ distinct approaches to their central existential concern. Illuminating the similarity that connects each epic with its partner simultaneously casts into relief the contrasts that exist between them.
The connection between each pair of contrasting epics originates with the poems themselves and is reinforced by their early readers. Hence, examining how each epic set represents itself and how its self-representation informs its designation by its early exegetes makes sense. This designation continues today to influence not only interpretations of the epic set itself, but also the conceptions that literary critics offer of the epic genre.
The earliest influence on critical conceptions of epic is the portrayal that the Iliad and Odyssey present of their interrelationship. The poems’ self-reflection shapes the Classical (ca. 500–323 BCE) Greek notions of epic that found modern ideas of this kind of literature, and that thus must be taken into account in any classificatory study of the epic genre’s representative works.

The Iliad and Odyssey’s Single Self-Understanding

A contemporary critic who parallels the Iliad and the Odyssey enters an exegetical tradition as old as the works themselves, [1]for they attest their own association. Appropriately, the Iliad (an account of earlier events) introduces the appellation for such stories as itself, while the Odyssey (which picks up the Iliad’s plot line) pushes for its own place under this umbrella term.
In the Iliad, Achilles’ father figure Phoenix calls up kléa andrō̂n (men’s glorious deeds) at a point in the poem when the inclusion of Achilles’ own acts among these illustrious exploits appears to be at risk. Seeking to convince the soldier to set aside his anger at his commander Agamemnon and to return to combat, Phoenix plays on Achilles’ aspiration to prestige:

nûn d’ háma t’ autíka pollà didoî, tà d’ ópisthen hupéstē, 
ándras dè líssesthai epiproéēken arístous 
krinámenos katà laòn Akhaiïkón, hoí te soì autō̂i 
phíltatoi Argeíōn∙ tō̂n mḕ sú ge mûthon elénxēis 
mēdè pódas∙ prìn d’ oú ti nemessētòn kekholō̂sthai. 
hoútō kaì tō̂n prósthen epeuthómetha kléa andrō̂n 
hērṓōn, hóte kén tin’ epizáphelos khólos híkoi∙ 
dōrētoí te pélonto parárrētoí t’ epéessi.
But now [Agamemnon] is giving you many things at once, and has promised more to come,
and has sent men to entreat you,
having selected the best among the Achaean army, the men who are
dearest to you of the Argives. Nullify neither their appeal
nor their approach, though before that no one could blame you for being angry.
To this effect, too, we have heard the glorious deeds of men of yore—
warriors who, when waves of anger washed over them,
would be propitiated by presents and open to persuasive words.

Iliad 9.519–526

In trying to steer Achilles back to his storied trajectory, a path to poetic immortality, Phoenix aligns the Iliad—an inchoate account from his perspective because Achilles has yet to attain in battle the kléos that the Iliad is being composed to celebrate[2—and earlier tales that already have been entrenched within his society’s world view. By placing Achilles, the Iliad’s protagonist, on a par with characters known for their kléa, Phoenix implicitly adds the poem in its future full form to this repository of records of renown as he attempts to persuade the hero of the Iliad to reenter the Trojan War and thus to make possible the completion of this poem’s presently suspended composition.

The Odyssey argues for its own classification as one of the kléa andrō̂n as it portrays a poetic performance:

autàr epeì pósios kaì edētúos ex éron hénto, 
Moûs’ ár’ aoidòn anē̂ken aeidémenai kléa andrō̂n, 
oímēs tē̂s tót’ ára kléos ouranòn eurùn híkane, 
neîkos Odussē̂os kaì Pēleḯdeō Akhilē̂os, 
hṓs pote dērísanto theō̂n en daitì thaleíēi 
ekpáglois epéessin, ánax d’ andrō̂n Agamémnōn 
khaîre nóōi, hó t’ áristoi Akhaiō̂n dērióōnto.
But, when their desire for food and drink subsided,
the Muse incited the singer to sing of men’s glorious deeds
from that song whose glory at that time reached widespread heaven,
namely, the quarrel between Odysseus and Peleus’ son Achilles—
how they once wrangled at the gods’ bountiful banquet
with violent words, and the king of men, Agamemnon,
exulted at the idea that the best of the Achaeans were wrangling.

Odyssey 8.72–78

This conflict between Achilles and Odysseus symbolizes that the kléa andrō̂n encompass the Iliad and the Odyssey alike, as Nagy has hinted: “The quarrel between Achilles and Odysseus in the first song of [Phaeacian singer] Demodokos, viii 72–82, dramatizes the antithesis of two inherited central themes built into the Iliad and the Odyssey, namely, the qualifications of [their heroes] Achilles and Odysseus respectively for the title ‘best of the Achaeans.’ Their epic actions are striving to attain what is perhaps the most distinctive heroic epithet that the kléos of the Achaeans can confer upon a mortal. In the first song of Demodokos, the poet—or let us say Demodokos—comments not only on the Odyssey but also on the Iliad itself.” [3]

Nagy’s characterization of Achilles’ and Odysseus’ quintessential actions as “epic” raises the question of when the Iliad and Odyssey began to be regarded as epics rather than as kléa andrō̂n. In response, some people, even without examining any evidence, may sense that these poems are inextricable from the idea of epic. For most readers schooled in the Western tradition, for instance, the Iliad and Odyssey epitomize epic poetry, as they are the first epics that students of this tradition encounter (though perhaps in abridged form). [4These students’ assumption is borne out insofar as the Homeric poems have taken precedence etymologically, as well as experientially. The English word “epic” ultimately derives (via the Greek adjective epikós) from the Greek noun épos, [5the meaning of whose plural form, épea, expanded by neology to encompass “epic poetry or poem” in addition to “words.” More precisely, épos in the late eighth century BCE was “used widely in Homer to designate words, in contrast to mûthos, which applies instead to the content of the words.” [6However, by the early fifth century BCE, épos had come in its plural form to mean epic poetry as well, as attest works of the lyric poet Pindar (518–ca. 440 BCE) and the historian Herodotus (ca. 485–425 BCE). [7]

Pindar and Herodotus: Exegetes Identifying the Iliad and Odyssey as Epics

Nagy has noted that, “[a]s in the songs of Pindar, the figure of Homer is treated as the ultimate representative of epic in the prose of Herodotus (e.g. [Histories] 2.116–117).” [8I would go a step further to stress that the foremost epic exemplars for both Pindar and Herodotus were Homer’s Iliad and Odyssey. Although Pindar and Herodotus each count among Homer’s epic compositions at least one component of the Epic Cycle (a number of now-lost poems that were composed separately circa the seventh century BCE, but were subsequently collected as accounts of the creation of the gods, the Theban War, and the Trojan War), the Iliad and Odyssey are the paradigmatic epics in the eyes of these two later authors.

Pindar’s praise of the Iliad and Odyssey

Pindar, for example, styles the athlete Timodemus after performers of this epic pair, explicitly connecting the extensive compositions that the Homeridae ultimately will articulate with the run of wins that this competitor eventually will amass, and implicitly likening his own ability to immortalize Timodemus poetically through praise to these Homeric rhapsodes’ potential to memorialize illustrious heroes by reciting epics. Thus, Nemean 2 begins:

Hóthen per kaì Homērídai 
rhaptō̂n epéōn tà póll’ aoidoí 
árkhontai, Diòs ek prooimíou, kaì hód’ anḗr 
katabolàn hierō̂n agṓnōn nikaphorías dédektai prō̂ton, Nemeaíou [9
en poluumnḗtōi Diòs álsei.
Just as the Homeridae,
singers of epic poems pieced together,
start out for the most part with a prelude to Zeus, so too this man
has begun to collect victories in the sacred contests of Nemea
in Zeus’ celebrated sacred grove.

Nemean 2.1–5

That the word epéōn (epic poems) in this passage’s second line alludes to the Iliad and Odyssey is indicated by the scholia to Nemean 2.1d, whose description of the aforementioned rhapsodes includes “[t]he expression hekatéras tē̂s poiḗseōs ‘each of the two poems[,’ which] implies that the Iliad and the Odyssey are meant.” [10]

Moreover, Pindar refers to events in these epics as he parallels himself to Homer, the prototypical epic poet, [11in Isthmian 4:

kaì krésson’ andrō̂n kheirónōn 
ésphale tékhna katamárpsais’∙ íste mán Aíantos alkán, phoínion tàn opsíai 
en nuktì tamṑn perì hō̂i phasgánōi momphàn ékhei paídessin Hellánōn hósoi Trṓiand’ éban. 
all’ Hómērós toi tetímaken di’ anthrṓpōn, hòs autoû 
pâsan orthṓsais aretàn katà rhábdon éphrasen 
thespesíōn epéōn loipoîs athúrein. 
toûto gàr athánaton phōnâen hérpei, 
eí tis eû eípēi ti∙ kaì pánkarpon epì khthóna kaì dià pónton bébaken 
ergmátōn aktìs kalō̂n ásbestos aieí. 
prophrónōn Moisân túkhoimen, keînon hápsai pursòn húmnōn 
kaì Melíssōi, pankratíou stephánōm’ epáxion, 
érneï Telesiáda. tólmai gàr eikṓs 
thumòn eribremetân thērō̂n leóntōn 
en pónōi, mē̂tin d’ alṓpēx, aietoû há t’ anapitnaména rhómbon iskhei∙ 
khrḕ dè pân érdont’ amaurō̂sai tòn ekhthrón. 
ou gàr phúsin Oariōneían élakhen∙ 
all’ onotòs mèn idésthai, 
sumpeseîn d’ akmâi barús.
And the skill of inferior men
overtakes and overthrows the mightier man. No doubt you know of the might of Ajax, which he slew bloodily late
at night with his own sword, being blamed as a result by all of the Greeks’ sons who traveled to Troy.
But Homer has honored him among people,
having gotten straight and recounted his every heroic act in the measured verse
of divine epic poems for successors to sing.
For, if someone says something well, it issues forth as an immortal utterance;
and over the earth full of all kinds of fruit and through the sea has ranged
the splendor of noble deeds, never to be extinguished.
May I gain the grace of the Muses so that I may ignite this torch of song
for Melissus too—for this offshoot of Telesiadas, a wreath worthy of his boxing-and-wrestling contest.
For in courage his heart resembles
those of roaring lions
in the thick of fighting, but in craftiness he is like a fox, which stays the swoop of an eagle by tumbling to its back.
The man must do anything to enfeeble his enemy.
For he was not allotted Orion’s size,
but rather summons scorn on sight.
His strength, however, makes him hard to combat hand-to-hand.

Isthmian 4.34–51

I have translated the word epéōn in line 39 as “epic poems” in order to emphasize the sources that supply Pindar with the material from which he fashions his own poetic persona. He begins this passage by citing the suicide of Ajax depicted in the Aethiopis (scholium to Isthmian 4.58b), but quickly contrasts with the warrior’s demise his heroism highlighted in the Iliad and indicated in the Odyssey. Thus, although Pindar—like most of his colleagues—probably attributed the Aethiopis and other Cyclic epics to Homer, he associated Homer’s expertise as an epic author with the Iliad and Odyssey.

Pindar’s privileging here of the Iliad over the Aethiopis has been discussed by classicist Frank J. Nisetich, who traces Ajax’s suicide to the Aethiopis and his praise to the Iliad. [12Indeed, in its assessment of the warriors in the Achaean army, the Iliadranks Ajax second only to Achilles, the epic’s hero (Iliad 2.768–769, 17.279–280). Yet, I disagree for two reasons with Nisetich’s assertion that the Homer whom Pindar esteems so highly in the Isthmian excerpt above is the poet only of the Iliad. [13First, even in the Odyssey, after the Trojan War has ended, Ajax—in the eyes of Odysseus, the epic’s own Achaean hero, no less—continues to rate right below Achilles, as Nisetich himself acknowledges. [14Second, and more significantly, the hero whom Homer “has honored” (tetímaken) in Isthmian 4.37 is not simply Ajax, as Nisetich argues, [15but also Odysseus.
The hero’s double identity here hinges on an ambiguity in Isthmian 4 to which its scholiasts have attended (scholia to Isthmian4.58c–d; 4.63a, b–c). The inference that Homer is said to have immortalized Ajax in Isthmian 4.37 follows from Pindar’s portrayal of Ajax’s self-destruction in the same poem. After explaining that Ajax has incurred the Achaean army’s censure by taking his own life, Pindar about-faces to emphasize how Homer has restored the warrior’s reputation (Isthmian 4.35–42). Pindar thus contrasts Ajax’s blame by the army to his praise by Homer.
Yet Pindar also may be opposing the stealthy shrewdness of Ajax’s physically overmatched opponent Odysseus in the Iliad and the Odyssey to the poetic publicity that Homer provides for Odysseus in these epics. Appropriately, Pindar initially only intimates Odysseus’ surreptitiousness, by advancing an aphorism (“… the skill of inferior men / overtakes and overthrows the mightier man. …” [… krésson’ andrō̂n kheirónōn / ésphale tékhna katamárpsais’∙ …] [Isthmian 4.34–35]) that the encounter of Ajax and Odysseus in Iliad 23.700–739 instances. Here, the two take part in a wrestling contest in honor of their deceased compatriot Patroclus, and Ajax appears at first to have the upper hand—both literally and figuratively—once he has hoisted Odysseus. Odysseus, however, surprises Ajax by hitting him on the back of his knee so that he falls backward; and, not long afterward, Achilles intercedes and awards the same prizes to both warriors. Their next confrontation, which occurs after Achilles’ death (and thus without his intervention), is much more one-sided. As Odysseus recalls in Odyssey 11.543–551, he and Ajax vie for Achilles’ arms; the contest judges—a group of Trojan men and Athena, the goddess of wisdom and war who is known in the Odyssey for her partiality to Odysseus—grant him the weapons; and Ajax dies as a result (as the Aethiopis makes explicit). Although Odysseus does not describe himself deceiving Ajax in their second struggle, Pindar seems to presume such a stratagem, elaborating the outcome of this engagement—Ajax’s suicide—immediately after alluding to Odysseus’ underhandedness in their first one. In fact, in Pindar’s own retelling in Nemean 8 of Ajax and Odysseus’ second conflict, the poet accuses Odysseus of swaying the contest judges (who are Achaeans rather than Trojans) with his lies (Nemean 8.25–26). The reason Pindar recasts the judges as Achaeans can be inferred from the contrast that Nisetich draws between the Homeric and Pindaric accounts of the contest. On the basis of the scholia to Odyssey 11.547, Nisetich deduces that “Agamemnon asked the Trojan captives named together with Athena as judges in line 547 who had hurt them more, Ajax or Odysseus; presumably, Athena moved them to name Odysseus. There is not much room here for the operation of Odysseus’ rhetorical skills, of which Pindar makes so much in Nemean 8.” [16Pindar, in his quest to demonstrate Odysseus’ deceit, thus alters the identity of the judges so that Odysseus has an audience likely to be receptive to his deceptive report of his heroic deeds.
In keeping, then, with the furtiveness for which Odysseus is known, Pindar places him at the periphery of Isthmian 4, centering instead on the unfortunate Ajax. And, even when acknowledging Odysseus’ acclaim, the poet omits this hero’s name (Isthmian4.37). But Pindar makes two motions toward Odysseus. First, Pindar hints in line 39 that Odysseus’ heroism extends through “epic poems” (epéōn), through the Iliad as well as the Odyssey. Indeed, if Iliadic Ajax, after his death, appears memorably in the Odyssey as Odysseus attempts to reconcile with him (this appearance occasioning Odysseus’ remembrance of their last dispute), Odyssean Odysseus advances to the fore in the Iliad while still alive. For instance, as Nagy has noticed, [17even though Odysseus—along with Ajax—originally is assigned to follow Phoenix in the Achaean embassy sent to soothe Achilles after Agamemnon has insulted him, Odysseus ends up at its lead (Iliad 9.168–169, 192).
Pindar also points to Odysseus by commenting in Isthmian 4.40–42 on the persistence and pervasiveness of poetry, for in Pindar’s characterization of poetic speech as immortal and spanning the fruitful earth as well as the sea are compressed several of the images that an incognito Odysseus himself once employed in Odyssey 19.107–114. Here, disguised as Aethon the beggar, he tells his wife, Penelope, that her glory reaches heaven—as does that of a righteous king for whom the earth produces grain; the trees, fruit; and the sea, fish. This king’s identity is evinced by Odysseus’ earlier avowal that his own glory extends to heaven, and by the abundance of his orchards (Odyssey 9.20, 24.336–344).
For his part, Pindar, by suggesting in Isthmian 4 that his patron Melissus has two faces (both Odysseus’ and Ajax’s), can exalt through imitation the Odyssey as much as the Iliad. Pindar’s perspective on the parity of these epics also informs his equal address in Isthmian 4.45–47 of Melissus’ leonine bravery and vulpine craftiness, for the poet’s focus here on his patron’s “heart” (thumòn) and “cunning” (mē̂tin) harks back to the Homeric opposition between the heroes of the Iliad and the Odyssey. While Achilles is labeled “lionhearted” (thumoléonta) and likened to a “lion” (léōn) that “has given way to its great power and bold heart” (… megálēi te bíēi kaì agḗnori thumō̂i / eíxas …), Odysseus is tagged not only as polúmētis (crafty in many ways), but also as poikilomḗtēs (crafty in various ways) (Iliad 7.228; 24.41, 42–43; 1.311; Odyssey 2.173; Iliad 11.482; Odyssey 3.163)—an even more meaningful epithet in light of the fact that poikílos (subtle) is among “[t]he most common adjectives applied to the fox.” [18]
Even though Pindar alludes to the opposition between Achilles and Odysseus in the course of characterizing Melissus, the poet prefaces his praise by commenting on the conflict between Ajax and Odysseus, because it is better suited to the immediate purpose of the poem—honoring Melissus for his military prowess. The bouts between Ajax and Odysseus in the Iliad and Odyssey pit brawn against brain. While these epics oppose Achilles and Odysseus on a similar basis (the distinction between their respective attributes of bíē and mē̂tis being a topos treated by Nagy [19), the heroes’ sole face-off—an altercation in Odyssey 8.75–77—is verbal rather than martial, and thus is less appropriate than Ajax and Odysseus’ encounters as an emblem of Melissus’ capabilities in combat.
The only other evidence of Pindar’s employment of the plural form of épos to indicate a particular epic occurs in the Varia Historia of Roman writer Aelian (ca. 170–235 CE), who cites Pindar’s pronouncement that “[Homer,] lacking the means to marry his daughter off, gave her the Cypria epic to have as her dowry” ([Hómēros] aporō̂n ekdoûnai tḕn thugatéra, édōken autē̂i proîka ékhein tà épē tà Kúpria) (Pindar fragment 265, quoted in Varia Historia 9.15). Although the original context of Pindar’s comment currently is unavailable, this fragment probably is not part of anything tantamount to his treatment of the transmission of the Iliad and Odyssey. Unlike the aforementioned excerpts from Nemean 2 and Isthmian 4, which evince Pindar’s efforts to procure for himself the prestige of performers of the Iliad and Odyssey, his remark on Homer’s handing down of the Cypria (a Cyclic epic) seems simply to be a statement of fact. If, from Pindar’s perspective, the Iliad and Odyssey are immortal poems on a par with their prefacing prayers to Zeus (the king of the gods), the Cypria is a commodity in a human transaction. Pindar thus places the Iliad and Odyssey in a celestial sphere consonant with his own lofty poetic aspirations, but relegates the Cypria to a mundane realm consistent with quotidian concerns. Hence the relevance of classicist Edward Fitch’s assertion “To say that Pindar knew and followed the Cypria and held the Cypria to be Homeric is not to affirm that the Cypria was as great as the Iliad[or, for that matter, the Odyssey], or that Pindar was undiscerning.” [20]

Herodotus’ attribution of the Iliad and Odyssey

The Iliad and Odyssey also are elevated above Cyclic epics in Herodotus’ Histories, albeit in another way. While he does not distinguish what he sees as the best epics from others in the Histories on the basis of literary merits, [21he conveys his preferences through his attribution of the epics. [22The power of attribution has been theorized by philosopher Michel Foucault, for whom “an author’s name … serves as a means of classification,” as it “can group together a number of texts and thus differentiate them from others” because of being one of the determinants of “[t]he meaning and value attributed to [a] text.”[23The appellation whose ascription carried such a cachet in Herodotus’ time was “Homer,” as the Histories make clear. Although Herodotus credits the contemporaries Hesiod and Homer [24with “creating genealogies of gods for the Greeks, giving those gods their names, specifying their spheres of influence and skills, and indicating their appearances” (poiḗsantes theogoníēn Héllēsi kaì toîsi theoîsi tàs epōnumías dóntes kaì timás te kaì tékhnas dielóntes kaì eídea autō̂n sēmḗnantes) (Histories 2.53.2), Homer seems to have a stronger hold on this historian than does Hesiod. In Herodotus’ eyes, Homer’s expertise applies to the everyday and the exotic alike.
More precisely, Herodotus reports in Histories 7.161.3 that Iliad 2.552–554 was cited by the Athenian representative in the Greek delegation sent to Sicily before the Greeks defeated the Persians at sea at Salamis in 480 BCE, in support of his opposition to Sicilian command of the Athenian navy. In this excerpt from the Iliad, the Athenian leader Menestheus is praised for his military prowess:

tō̂n aûth’ hēgemóneu’ huiòs Peteō̂o Menestheús. 
tō̂i d’ oú pṓ tis homoîos epikhthónios génet’ anḕr 
kosmē̂sai híppous te kaì anéras aspidiṓtas∙
what is more, these [young Athenian men] were led by Peteus’ son, Menestheus.
And there was no man at all on earth
who could array horses and shield-carrying men as he could …

Iliad 2.552–554

In referring to this passage, Herodotus’ Athenian delegate evokes Iliad 2.556 (where Menestheus is said to have led a force of fifty ships) and thereby counters the inferior alternative of Sicilian supervision.

In addition to mentioning this Athenian referencing of Menestheus’ heroism, Herodotus himself adduces Odyssey 4.85 to bolster his belief that Scythian bovines are hornless because they are subject to harsh weather (Histories 4.29). Herodotus thus contrasts the frigid Scythian climate with the heat in Libya, “where lambs become horned soon after they are born” (hína t’ árnes áphar keraoì teléthousi) (Odyssey 4.85). In a comment on Histories 4.29, classicists W. W. How and J. Wells opine that “H[erodotus] uses Homer as [thei]r [English] ancestors used the Bible, to prove everything.” [25Indeed, Herodotus’ references to the Iliad and the Odyssey for his culture’s last words on Athenian authority and cornute physiology, respectively, lend credence to classicist Eric A. Havelock’s concept of the “Homeric Encyclopedia”—his idea that “in the compendious epic[s] of Homer [are] contained all philosophy and all history and all science.” [26]
Like Pindar, Herodotus does not denote only the Iliad and Odyssey with the plural of épos. Yet the historian differs from the poet in his means of setting apart these epics from their Cyclic counterparts. Whereas Pindar reserves for the Iliad and Odyssey the kind of praise that he hopes that his own compositions will elicit eventually, Herodotus regards the two poems as the only epics that Homer authored indubitably, and thereby calls into question Homer’s connection to the Cyclic poems. For example, Herodotus observes that Homer has mentioned the Hyperboreans in the Epigoni, but quickly qualifies this statement with the phrase “if in fact Homer composed this epic” (ei dḕ tō̂i eónti ge Hómēros taûta tà épea epoíēse) (Histories 4.32). In the case of the Cypria, moreover, Herodotus does not merely interrogate, but rather altogether denies, Homeric authorship: “[T]he Cypriaepic is not by Homer but by someone else” (ouk Homḗrou tà Kúpria épeá esti all’ állou tinós) (Histories 2.117).
Herodotus’ suspicions about the origins of the Cyclic epics suggest that “the Homeric epics” (tō̂n Homēreíōn epéōn) whose recitation he says King Cleisthenes cuts off in his city, Sicyon, “because the Argives and Argos are exalted almost throughout them” (hóti Argeîoí te kaì Árgos tà pollà pánta humnéatai) include at least the Iliad and the Odyssey (Histories 5.67.1): “[T]he constant use [in the Iliad and the Odyssey] of ‘Argives’ for Greeks, and the position of Agamemnon as overlord of Sicyon, would be an offence to Cleisthenes, [even if] it [is] … probable that H[erodotus] here [in Histories 5.67.1] … refers to the Thebais[, a Cyclic epic] which began Árgos áeide, théa, poludípsion [‘Sing, goddess, of parched Argos …’], and to the Epigoni[,] in which Adrastus must have played a great part.” [27Although Adrastus the Argive, whose worship Cleisthenes seeks to stop in Sicyon (Histories 5.67), figures prominently in the Thebais as well as in the Epigoni, Herodotus was less likely to ascribe to Homer these epics than the Iliad and the Odyssey. Moreover, Adrastus also appears in Iliad 2.572, as Sicyon’s first king.
Another way in which Herodotus highlights the Homeric composition of the Iliad and Odyssey is by coining terms for this type of poetry and its maker. [28Herodotus invents the new genre name as he speculates that Homer heard the story of how Proteus had hosted Helen of Sparta in Memphis, but did not include this tale in the Iliad “because it was not as well suited to an epic poem as the other [story] of which he did make use” (ou gàr homoíōs es tḕn epopoiíēn euprepḕs ē̂n tō̂i hetérōi tō̂i per ekhrḗsato) (Histories 2.116.1 [emphasis added]). Herodotus dubs Homer an “epic poet” (epopoiòs) in the course of citing his praise of Athenian power in the Iliad (Histories 7.161.3). The application of these two new terms (epopoiíē and epopoiós) in connection to the Odyssey as well as to the Iliad is implied both by Herodotus’ inclusion of Odyssean as well as Iliadic passages as he presents Homer’s references to Helen’s stay in Egypt, soon after employing the word epopoiíēn (the singular accusative form of epopoiíē); and by the similar way in which Herodotus relies on the Odyssey for rhetorical support as he does on the Iliad, whose source he sees as the aforementioned epopoiós (Iliad 6.289–292 and Odyssey 4.227–230, 351–352, quoted in Histories 2.116.3–5). In How and Wells’ estimation, the Odyssean extracts “are probably interpolations,” as Herodotus does not go on to discuss them. [29But, even if Herodotus himself did not adduce any of the Odyssey to demonstrate what an epic poem entailed, the fact that some redactor of his deemed Odyssean material appropriate to incorporate into his description is telling. If, in this regard, “the question to ask is not where the disparate elements originated, but why they were put together, and why kept together,” [30at least one answer is that, in light of the remainder of the Histories, the Odyssey exemplifies Homer’s epic poetry no less than does the Iliad, and thus contains the kind of plot elements that Herodotus would have expected to find in one of Homer’s epic poems.
Herodotus, by adding forms of the verb poiéō (to make) to the noun épos to create the compounds epopoiós and epopoiíē, emphasizes the process of producing epic poems and thus calls attention to their composer, Homer. Thus, in Herodotus’ eyes, as in those of his precursor Pindar, Homer appears already to have assumed the cloak of a “culture hero” whose existence has been explained by Nagy:

For the ancient Greeks, … Homer was not just the creator of epic par excellence: he was also the culture hero of epic itself. Greek institutions tend to be traditionally retrojected, by the Greeks themselves, each to a protocreator, a culture hero who is credited with the sum total of a given cultural institution. It was a common practice to attribute any major achievement of society, even if this achievement may have been realized only through a lengthy period of social evolution, to the episodic and personal accomplishment of a culture hero who is pictured as having made his monumental contribution in an earlier era of the given society. Greek myths about lawgivers, for example, whether the lawgivers are historical figures or not, tend to reconstruct these figures as the originators of the sum total of customary law as it evolved through time. So also with Homer: he is retrojected as the original genius of epic. [31]

And, just as Homer is the paragon of epic poets for Pindar and Herodotus, the Iliad and Odyssey are their ideal epics. [32]

The Ongoing Elevation of the Iliad and Odyssey in the Twentieth Century

The emphasis that Pindar and Herodotus place on this pair of poems echoes in recent criticism. Twentieth-century critics, like the early exponents of Homer, single (or perhaps double) the Iliad and Odyssey out from the Greek epic corpus, with labels as lofty as “the noble epithets” [33that the two poems themselves employ. On epic epithets, classicist G. S. Kirk comments: “The use of conventional decorative epithets is an essential part of the Greek epic style, and lends to the Homeric poetry much of its rich and formal texture. Each individual character, object or event is treated as a perfect member of its species, and is expressed in the way determined as best for the species as a whole. This tendency to describe individuals in generic terms implies a certain way of looking at things: a simplified, synthetic way.” [34Seen in such a way, the Iliad and Odyssey are “great epics,” [35“monumental compositions” [36of “influence.” [37]
In comparison suffer their successors, the Cyclic epics. In the current absence of these works, contemporary critics assume that ancient exegetes assessed the poems correctly. On this assessment, the Cyclic epics are dismissed as being derivative: “Aristotle, Callimachus, and everyone else who mentions the Epic Cycle poems remark on their obvious inferiority to the Homeric poems. They seem to have been composed in order to create a chronology in epic narrative of all the events from the origin of the world to the death of Odysseus, which is what we might call the end of the heroic period.” [38Earlier, Kirk similarly asserts that these works were “designed [expressly] to fill gaps left by Homer, … to fill in those aspects of the Trojan adventure not described in the Iliad or Odyssey.” [39]
Seeing the Cyclic epics simply as supplements to the Iliad and Odyssey allows their modern readers to elevate this pair of earlier poems above subsequent works. From the perspective of these interpreters, not only were the Cyclic epics “clearly inferior to the Iliad and Odyssey,” but the “distinction between Homeric and Cyclic [works] … was due to the exceptional genius that went into the creation of the two Homeric epics.” [40This perspective thus proceeds from the assumption that the Iliad and the Odyssey are magna opera sui generis, the acme of all poetic compositions past and to come: “The utter collapse of the creative epic spirit as shown in the poetry of the Epic Cycle, if we base our opinion of the merits of these poems on the estimate of competent ancient authorities, shows that Homer had no successors. The Iliad and the Odyssey represent the golden age of epic poetry, and golden ages are always brief.” [41At least part of the luster of the Homeric poems is lent by their “Panhellenic” outlook. While the Cyclic epics take up topics local to particular city-states, the Iliad and Odyssey meld the traditions of these areas into an amalgam that reflects local colors in the light of close examination, but that combines them to emit a characteristic spectrum. [42]
Yet separating the Homeric epics radically from their Cyclic counterparts uproots both sets of poems from the common ground of their shared mythological tradition. While both the Homeric and the Cyclic works likely grew at least partly independently out of an older body of heroic stories, considering the Iliad and Odyssey as this corpus’ crowning glory requires reconceiving and relocating the Cyclic epics as limbs newly added to connect the Homeric canopy to its onetime trunk. In this misguiding light, the Cyclic poems seem to have been transplanted after the fact, as missing links between the Homeric epics and their narrative antecedents. More likely, however, the Cyclic epics are the younger offshoots of a largely separate branch belonging to the same storied tree. [43]
Misconstruing the relationship between the Homeric and Cyclic epics as one of sheer dependence of the latter on the former offers the distinct advantage of pinpointing in the Iliad and Odyssey the pinnacle of the ancient Greek poetic tradition. To this effect, classicist Cedric H. Whitman suggests that, in spite of subsequent literary production, the Homeric epics endure as their culture’s most prominent representatives: “In the long run, both Iliad and Odyssey contributed their share to the perfecting of what we call the classical spirit. Embodying as they do the polarities of that spirit, they remain for us the archetypes of the Classical, the Hellenic.” [44In the eyes of yet other readers, including classicist Charles Rowan Beye, the influence of the Homeric epics is even wider, crossing cultural and temporal divides. Thus, “for [these] literary historians and theorists the very notion of epic poetry ultimately derives from the Homeric texts.” [45]
But, although Whitman and Beye consider the Iliad and Odyssey to be prototypes, these critics do not claim that the poems possess no predecessors. While Whitman emphasizes the immense contribution that the Iliad and Odyssey have made to ancient Greek culture, he acknowledges their own debt to earlier works. In a later study, he states: “Homer’s poems bear on every page the tokens of oral composition within a traditional verse medium reaching back for centuries into the unexplorable dimness of the Indo-European past.” [46By the same “tokens,” Beye allows that “one may argue that the Greeks inherited epic poetry in dactylic hexametric rhythm from their Indo-European ancestors,” even after he has identified the Homeric works as the source of the epic idea. [47]
The Iliad and Odyssey thus imitate as well as innovate, as their identification as epics implies. As a particular kind of composition, the Iliad and Odyssey resemble poems that preceded them, but at the same time have brought to the literary world something new that has become inextricable from the idea of what an epic is. This apparent paradox of originary model poems made in the mold of older ones usefully highlights the constructed character of the Homeric compositions’ archetypicality. Recognizing that the Iliad and Odyssey themselves have poetic ancestors, in spite of being represented as the first forebears of a poetic tradition, reveals that interpretative pains have been taken to portray the Homeric poems as prototypes. This portrayal probably arose from two attributes of the Iliad and Odyssey. First, they are the earliest attested works of ancient Greek literature, so critics studying this corpus conveniently see these extant compositions as its head and ascribe an identity to this body on the basis of the poem pair’s features. Second, the Iliad and Odyssey have long inspired aesthetic appreciation, and thus seem to be suitable exemplars for subsequent literary efforts. [48Even if somehow recovered and proved to precede the Homeric poems, the Cyclic epics would be hard pressed to dethrone them as standards of artistic beauty, because—no matter what current critics beheld—they probably would still heed the dissatisfaction with the Cyclic poems that has been resounding for centuries.
The longstanding influence that the Iliad and Odyssey have had on later literary composition and criticism explains why identifying what these works contribute to the conception of epic that they inaugurated is important. This conception—which would serve as a standard of composition and comparison not only for ancient Greek authors and exegetes, but also for their counterparts in later periods and other lands—can be clarified by applying philosopher Panayot Butchvarov’s idea of generic identity.

Generic identity and the Homeric epics

“Generic identity” is a relationship between the quality of one individual and the quality of another, such that the characteristic specific to each quality (and thus not possessed by the other) depends logically on the characteristic that these qualities share (i.e. their generic characteristic). In the “classical example of [the] generic identity … of an equilateral [triangle] and an isosceles triangle,” the generic characteristic common to the qualities of these figures (which are equilateral triangularity and isosceles triangularity) is triangularity itself, and the specific characteristic of each quality (having three equal sides in the case of equilateral triangularity or having two equal sides in the case of isosceles triangularity) is contingent on the generic characteristic (triangularity). Therefore, equilateral triangularity and isosceles triangularity are generically, though not specifically, identical. [49]
This account of generic identity applies to the classification of the Iliad and Odyssey as epics. “Iliadness” and “Odysseyness,” the respective qualities of the Homeric poems, share “epicness,” their generic characteristic; and the specific characteristics of these qualities—namely, being unique to the Iliad and being unique to the Odyssey—are a subset of epicness.
Also pertinent to the equation of epic poetry and the Homeric texts is another aspect of generic identity: the fact that the quality of an individual has a generic characteristic means that this quality must have only one of a limited range of specific characteristics. Stated another way, the quality’s generic characteristic must manifest as one of the specific characteristics that the quality can possess. Take, for example, triangles again: “[W]hile an instance of being a figure enclosed by three lines need not be an instance of equilateral triangularity, it must be an instance of some one of the logically possible species of being a figure enclosed by three lines, i.e., the lengths of its three sides must be proportioned in one of the several ways which alone are logically possible. It cannot be an instance of triangularity unless it is an instance … of equilateral or isosceles or scalene triangularity.” [50For those who see epic poetry and the Homeric works as being synonymous, the generic characteristic of epicness is instantiated in Iliadness or Odysseyness. Epicness, or the conception of epic that originates with the Homeric works, is constructed from the attributes common to the Iliad and the Odyssey, and therefore amounts to the overlap of Iliadness and Odysseyness. Inspecting the features shared by the Homeric poems shows that these traits compose portraits of epic form and content.

Epicness in form

The form that epic assumes consists in similarities between the Iliad and the Odyssey in scale, structure, and style. In scale, the compositions are extensive, each containing twenty-four books averaging somewhat fewer than 660 lines each in the Iliad and more than 500 lines each in the Odyssey. Yet the epics’ extent is a matter not merely of length but additionally of depth. If “[e]verything is presented [in the poems] on a huge canvas[,] … sketched in … large outlines,” [51these lines have been filled in with detailed designs rather than broad brushstrokes. The expanse of the epics’ forests fails to overshadow the intricacy of the veins in their trees’ leaves.
The extent of the epics is supported by their structure—an outgrowth of repetition, ring composition, and multiplication. About one-third of the lines in the Iliad appear elsewhere in the poem, and the same goes for the Odyssey. Additionally, the story line of each epic comes full circle. For instance, the Iliad’s first and last books both feature an angry Achilles speaking with his mother, divine Thetis, the sea nymph who intercedes for him with Zeus. Similarly, the Odyssey opens and closes with the goddess Athena descending from Mount Olympus to the island of Ithaca in order to aid Odysseus and his son Telemachus. Yet, as patly as the epics end, they delay their denouements, sustaining narrative tension through their twenty-second books’ climaxes. What postpones the peaking of the epics’ plots until the eleventh hour is the incessant interposition of episodes. In each poem, approximately twenty-two hundred lines separate the turning point from the climax, so there is a similar prolonging of the plot line between Odysseus’ return to his palace and slaying of the suitors in the Odyssey as between Achilles’ decision to avenge Patroclus and assailing of Hector in the Iliad. [52]
Thus, the structure of the Homeric epics is such that audiences wending their way through the woods of the Iliad and of the Odyssey retrace some steps and sidetrack while circumambulating. Beneath the strollers’ feet, both paths parallel the styles of these poems, and thus are made of the same materials. The Iliad and the Odyssey exhibit like styles, relying on like types of poetic formulae and language.

Epicness in content

The ground common to the epic forests that underlies their trees, as well as their paths, is their poetic tradition. The plot of this land on which the Iliad and the Odyssey stand yields four types of trees, four themes that constitute columns of epic content:

  1. The hero’s need to separate himself from his social surroundings
  2. His social surroundings’ destabilization by conflict
  3. His ability to reorder his life
  4. His mortal limits
To make a name for himself, an epic hero has to act exceptionally. Yet action in the epics is inextricable from a nexus of social relationships. The strong connections between warriors and their families and compatriots put recognizable faces on the society that would celebrate the successes of these fighters or deride their defeats, and provide a social context for the men’s individual deeds. [53A man who hopes to be a hero, however, can cement his local status only by isolating himself from others:

Whether for wealth or reputation or by a code that demands leadership in adventure, a hero cannot tamely stay home. In the so-called shame-society and at a time before the protections of formal law, a man’s standing with dependents and rivals turns on his will to demonstrate his power. Nothing will protect him if he fails to do so. But if he leaves home, he moves into a world the width and complexity of which only the gods fully know, yet which as a man of position he expects to master. The task will prove impossible on those assumptions. Great heroes will owe their fame to their self-fidelity in face of the fact. True to themselves, they will have moved out toward command and glory and will die when it becomes evident that safe return was not among the first conditions. On this view, the Iliad as much as the Odyssey concerns the relationship of home to the world. Both poems turn on the hard paradox that to stay home will, by a man’s loss of wealth and reputation, undermine home and obscure its relation to the gods’ wide world, yet to venture out will reveal enormity and danger and make return unlikely. [54]

Yet venture out the Homeric heroes must, and enter the fights forged by their aspirations, for conflict creates opportunities for these men to prove their martial prowess. While the seizure of the Spartan queen Helen and its aftermath incite Achilles to lay down the lives of legions as well as his own on the Trojan battlefield, the encroachment of the suitors upon Odysseus’ Ithacan estate spurs him to slaughter them after his arduous journey home.

However, even though the heroes ultimately mend rends in their societies’ social fabrics by working to reunite Helen and Penelope with their husbands, there is more to the Iliad and the Odyssey than their third “theme of restored order.” [55The paradox in which the poems’ heroes are placed as they exchange the ill-regarded security of home for the prestigious prospect of faraway success that necessarily remains unreachable has even larger implications to which classicist John H. Finley, Jr., has pointed. Once epic heroes leave home, they strive to prove themselves while discovering that they are less than divine. [56]Whitman develops this idea by describing these characters’ condition as “the heroic paradox,” the contradiction that they live as they attempt to emulate gods, in spite of confronting human constraints. [57The route to which Achilles and Odysseus resort in order to escape this paradox is a path to poetic immortality. Although the men themselves cannot elude death, they can achieve kléos—and thereby live on in epic song.
Nevertheless, the Homeric heroes do not transcend their paradox, which actually is a prerequisite of their stories. Epics, as Doniger has discussed, are associated intimately with myths, narratives that “raise religious questions” and that “wrestle with insoluble paradoxes[—]as [anthropologist] Claude Lévi-Strauss noted long ago[—that] they inevitably fail to pin … to the mat.”[58If, as Lévi-Strauss asserts, “the purpose of myth is to provide a logical model capable of overcoming a contradiction (an impossible achievement if, as it happens, the contradiction is real),” [59and if the Iliad and the Odyssey address the heroic paradox, then it makes sense that these epics (like their counterparts in other cultures) feature, in Doniger’s words, “the constant interaction of the two planes, the human and the divine,” [60without allowing them to merge. By interacting with their anthropomorphic gods, Achilles and Odysseus become aware of the full measure of the power which they themselves may aspire to, if only imperfectly personify.
Although Olympus-like heights lie off-limits to Achilles and Odysseus, the Iliad and Odyssey occupy a privileged place atop their poetic tradition. Yet losing sight of the critical influences that have lifted them above other literary works leaves the Homeric poems aloft at an Archimedean point in the heavens, with these epics’ connections to subsequent texts unwitnessed. Seeing such works as the Iliad and Odyssey as nearly unreachable benchmarks of the epic genre has two drawbacks, as classicist J. B. Hainsworth has observed. First, such single-minded sight blinds onlookers to later uses of the term “epic” in senses that may be separate from the poems that first bear its standard. Second, the spectators regard as deficient those works that differ from these Platonic forms of epics. [61]
These two problems threaten to cloud the surroundings of the Homeric poems in such a way that they seem likely to soar in mid-air, above not only other texts of the same tradition, but also similar texts of other traditions. Fortunately, however, the fresh zephyrs of two analyses keep clear the epics’ rarified air, and account for their abstraction from works of their own and other cultures. One analysis, involving generic identity, has shown how the notion of epic has been built from the attributes of the Iliadand Odyssey, rather than from the attributes of later Greek texts, and thus indicates that this concept could be reconstructed from the characteristics of other apparently ur-works. The other analysis, which will make use of metaphor, will exhibit the reconstruction of the epic idea on the basis of two ancient Indian poems. Thus, I will turn to these works, the Rāmāyaṇa and the Mahābhārata, in Chapter 2.

Footnotes

back ] 1. I assume that the Homeric epics were composed more or less simultaneously in the latter half of the eighth century BCE, because problems with definitively dating these texts preclude me from arguing that the affirmative Iliad preceded the interrogative Odyssey.
back ] 2. Classicist Andrew Ford (1992:109) makes a similar point while analyzing the epic poem that Phemius performs in the first book of the Odyssey: “The fundamental character of epic as poetry of the past is reversed when it appears in the looking glass of epic. What were the ‘fames of men’ for Homer’s audience were fresh rumor and recent news for the heroes; the literate’s trope would be to say that the faded parchments we keep in museums were the daily newspapers of old. And this makes sense, for it is an appropriate glorification of these men greater than we to say that, just as their own deeds and lives are destined to become the stuff of immortal poetry, so the poetry they prefer comes closest to these deeds.”
back ] 3. Nagy 1999:59. An earlier version of the following two paragraphs has appeared in Pathak 2013:36–37.
back ] 4. Summaries of the Iliad and Odyssey include those prepared by mythographer Thomas Bulfinch (1912:220–232, 241–262) and by classicist Edith Hamilton (1942:178–192, 202–219) for their popular mythological compendia. An even briefer account of the epics that is addressed to even younger readers appears in children’s book authors Ingri and Edgar Parin d’Aulaire’s (1962:183–184) Book of Greek Myths.
back ] 5. Oxford English Dictionary 1989–2013, s.v. “epic, a. and n.”
back ] 6. Chantraine 1984–1990, vol. 1, s.v. “épos”: “employé largement chez Hom. pour désigner les paroles, à côté demũthos qui s’applique plutôt au contenu des paroles.”
back ] 7. Liddell, Scott, and Jones 1940 (hereafter cited as LSJ), s.v. “épos,” IV.a.
back ] 8. Nagy 1990a:215.
back ] 9. Like classicist-poet Richmond Lattimore (1976:103), I read Nemeaíou with the rest of line 4 rather than with line 5. (In fact, C. M. Bowra [1935], the classicist who edited the text on which Lattimore’s translation is based, includes no comma between the words prō̂ton and Nemeaíou.)
back ] 10. Scholia to Nemean 2.1d, quoted in Nagy 1996b:84n56.
back ] 11. If Homer is “the protopoet whose poetry is reproduced by [a] continuous succession of [such] performers” as the Homeridae (Nagy 1996a:76), then Pindar seeks a spot at the end of this line.
back ] 12. Nisetich 1989:9.
back ] 13. Nisetich 1989:9–11.
back ] 14. Odyssey 11.469–470, 550–551, cited in Nisetich 1989:9.
back ] 15. Nisetich 1989:13.
back ] 16. Nisetich 1989:17.
back ] 17. Nagy 1999:49–50.
back ] 18. Detienne and Vernant 1978:35.
back ] 19. Nagy 1999:45–49, 61, 147, 317–321.
back ] 20. Fitch 1924:65.
back ] 21. Pfeiffer 1968–1976, vol. 1:44–45.
back ] 22. As classicist Barbara Graziosi (2002:168) has observed, “discussions about authors were a powerful way of expressing thoughts about [Archaic epic] poetry, especially at a time in which written texts were not the focus of attention.”
back ] 23. Foucault 1977:123, 126.
back ] 24. By Herodotus’ reckoning, Hesiod and Homer belong to the ninth century BCE, preceding him by no more than four centuries (Histories 2.53.2). Most scholars today, however, would place Hesiod’s poetry after Homer’s, in the early seventh century BCE. For perhaps the most vociferous dissenting view, see M. L. West’s (1966:46–47) prolegomena to the Theogony.
back ] 25. How and Wells 1912, vol. 1:4.29n.
back ] 26. Havelock 1963:61, 292.
back ] 27. How and Wells 1912, vol. 2:5.67.1n.
back ] 28. LSJ, s.vv. “epopoiía,” “epopoiós.”
back ] 29. How and Wells 1912, vol. 1:2.116.4n.
back ] 30. O’Flaherty 1973:12.
back ] 31. Nagy 1996b:21.
back ] 32. An earlier version of the current chapter’s remainder has appeared in Pathak 2013:37–43.
back ] 33. Crotty 1994:159.
back ] 34. Kirk 1962:80.
back ] 35. Kirk 1962:159, 265; Griffin 1977:39, 52; Thalmann 1984:182.
back ] 36. Nagy 1999:15; Redfield 1983:218; Pucci 1987:18.
back ] 37. Griffin 1987:86.
back ] 38. Beye 1993:30.
back ] 39. Kirk 1962:98, 254.
back ] 40. Griffin 1977:52, 53.
back ] 41. Scott 1921:243.
back ] 42. On this striking contrast between the Homeric and Cyclic epics, see Huxley 1969, Finley 1978:73, and Nagy 1999:7–8 and 2005:85, 86.
back ] 43. Burgess 2001:1, 5, 174–175, 134–145, 154–156. For an overview of the differences between the Homeric and Cyclic epics, see Burgess 2005:350–351.
back ] 44. Whitman 1958:309.
back ] 45. Beye 1993:x.
back ] 46. Whitman 1982:92.
back ] 47. Whitman 1982:92; Beye 1993:5.
back ] 48. If imitation is the sincerest form of flattery, then the Homeric poems have been complimented constantly as primary epics by the conscious composition of secondary, tertiary, quaternary, and quinary epics on the Homeric pair’s basis over succeeding centuries. For a survey of such developments, see Preminger et al. 1993, s.v. “EPIC.”
back ] 49. Butchvarov 1966:163–164, 165.
back ] 50. Butchvarov 1966:164, 166.
back ] 51. Scott 1921:267.
back ] 52. Scott 1921:262–263, 257–258.
back ] 53. Dodds 1951:17–18; Crotty 1994:211.
back ] 54. Finley 1978:42–43.
back ] 55. Finley 1978:194.
back ] 56. Finley 1978:211.
back ] 57. Whitman 1982:25, 22.
back ] 58. Doniger 1998:9, 2, 95.
back ] 59. Lévi-Strauss 1963:229.
back ] 60. Doniger 1998:9.
back ] 61. Hainsworth 1991:3–4.